BIOGRAPHICAL NOTICE OF ARTHUR CAYLEY.
XXXIX
To the theories of rational transformation and correspondence he made considerable
additions. Two figures are said to be rationally transformable into one another when
to a variable point of one of them corresponds reciprocally one (and only one) variable
point of the other. The figure may be a space or it may be a locus in a space.
Rational transformations between two spaces give rational transformations between loci
in those spaces; but it is not in general true that rational transformations between
two loci necessarily give rational transformations between the spaces in which those loci
exist. There is thus a distinction between the theory of transformation of spaces and
the theory of correspondence of loci. Both theories have occupied many investigators,
the latter in particular; and Cayley’s work may fairly be claimed to have added much
to the knowledge of the theory as due* to Riemann, Cremona and others.
Further, there may be singled out for special mention, his investigations on the
bitangents of plane curves, and, in particular, on the 28 bitangents of a non-singular
quartic; his developments of Pliicker’s conception of foci; his discussion of the osculating
conics of curves, and of the sextactic points on a plane curve (these are the places
where a conic can be drawn through six consecutive points); his contributions to the
geometrical theory of the invariants and covariants of plane curves; and his memoirs
on systems of curves subjected to specified conditions. Moreover, he was fond of making
models and of constructing apparatus intended for the mechanical description of curves.
The latter finds record in various of his papers; even so lately as 1893 he exhibited,
at a meeting of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, a curve-tracing mechanism con
nected with three-bar motion.
All the preceding results belong to plane geometry; no less important or less
numerous were the results he contributed to solid geometry. The twenty-seven lines
that lie upon a cubic surface were first announced in his memoirj*, “On the triple
tangent planes of surfaces of the third order,” published in 1849, after a corre
spondence between Salmon and himself. Cayley devised a new method for the analytical
expression of curves in space by introducing into the representation the cone passing
through the curve and having its vertex at an arbitrary point. Again, by using
Pliicker’s equations that connect the ordinary (simple) singularities of plane curves, he
deduced equations connecting the ordinary (simple) singularities of the developable surface
that is generated by the osculating plane of a given tortuous curve, and, therefore, also
of any developable surface. He greatly extended Salmon’s theory of reciprocal surfaces;
and resuming a subject already discussed by Schläfli he produced! in 1869 his “Memoir
on cubic surfaces,” in which he dealt with their complete classification. Many of his
memoirs are devoted to the theory of skew ruled surfaces, or scrolls as he called them.
Our knowledge of geodesics, of orthogonal systems of surfaces, of the centro-surface of
an ellipsoid, of the wave-surface, of the 16-nodal quartic surface, not to mention more,
* In this connexion a report by Brill and Noether, “Bericht über die Entwicklung der Theorie der
algebraischen Functionen in älterer und neuerer Zeit” (Jahresber. d. Deutschen Mathem.-Vereinigung, vol. in.
1894) will be found—particularly the sixth and the tenth sections—to give a very valuable resume of the
theory and its history.
t C. M. P. vol. i. No. 76; Camb. and Dull. Math. Jour. vol. iv. (1849), pp. 118—132. See also Salmon’s
Solid Geometry (third edition, 1874), p. 464, note.
t C. M. P. vol. vi. p. 412; Phil. Trans. (1869), pp. 231—326.
C. VIII.
/