ON PROBABILITY. 41
Vai in dM dX) eC ;
| do pot (F) and (2) may be calculated directly, but it is better to infer them by
%: 1
lope assuming an arbitrary error de, and by finding the corresponding error 6 \,
Sof da dX ;
If @ and b be put for F) and (2) the n” observation furnishes the
fiom oe equation ON, =a, de} 5,3,
and the two equations which serve to determine §e and 3 = by the method
of least syuares are
a 20ON,a,=3%e3 (a) +-w2a,b,
quant
By ZEN) b=3eSa,b,+3m3 5)
i (he ques. If only one quantity has to be determined, this method evidently resolves
iat sytem itself into taking the mean of all the values given by observation.
8 39,2, is 64. We shall now, in conclusion, trace the theory of probability through
the different stages of its progress, and mention the principal writers who
be the mst have assisted in establishing its principles. The estimation of the probability
0 that the of a future event, by enumeration of the cases supposed to be similarly circum-
stanced, does not appear to have been attempted until the early part of the
seventeenth century ; and the very elementary nature of the first problem of
which the solution is on record, serves to show that the subject was then
altogether new. It is contained in a fragment of uncertain date, written by
the celebrated Galileo, who died in 1642. It was addressed to a friend who
thought the fact that the points 9 and 10 can both be produced by six
different combinations of numbers on three dice difficult to reconcile with the
separately, notorious preference given by gamesters to the latter number beyond the
alls sena. former. The difficulty is explained by Galileo, by taking into account the
permutations of the component numbers, and the respective chances of these
two numbers are thus shown to be as 25 to 27. A correct table is subjoined
of the permutations of all numbers which can be thrown on three dice ; and
it is added, that the consideration of this table will serve for the solution of
other problems of the same nature. All this must be admitted to belong to
the infancy of the science, nor does it appear that Galileo thought the subject
of sufficient interest to call for further inquiry.
65. The history of the theory of probability is generally made to begin
several years later, when, in the year 1654, the two following problems were
proposed by the Chevalier de Meré to Blaise Pascal.
ad hence a Ist. Two players want each a given number of points towards winning.
a White If they separate without playing out the game, how should the stakes be
thousand divided between them ?
Heme. 2d. Inhow many trials is it an even wager to throw sixes upon two dice ?
1 2CCNTacy We are told in one of Pascal’s letters to Fermat, that his answer to the
seals by latter question, that the odds are against twenty-four trials, and in favour
of twenty-five, though undoubtedly correct, scandalized Mr. de Meré, and
om made him declare loudly that the science of arithmetic is inconsistent with
heen itself.”* The Chevalier thought that the chances being in favour of throw-
x abv ing six in four trials with one die, on which are six different numbers, they
hobs 4] ought also to be in favour of throwing two sixes in six times as many, or
Wi twenty-four trials with two dice, on which are six times as many, or thirty-
¢ Tar} six different numbers. Those who have read the preceding pages with any
degree of attention, will readily perceive that the Chevalier (whose name it
#¥ Opera Petri de Fermat, Tolose, 1679,