COMMENTARIES, CRITICISMS & REFERENCES 359
Other very early criticisms there were, directed against the
very first steps in Euclid’s work. Thus Zeno of Sidon, an
Epicurean, attacked the proposition I. 1 on the ground that it
is not conclusive unless it be first assumed that neither two
straight lines nor two circumferences can have a common
segment ; and this was so far regarded as a serious criticism
that Posidonius wrote a whole book to controvert Zeno. 1
Again, there is the criticism of the Epicureans that I. 20,
proving that any two sides in a triangle are together greater
than the third, is evident even to an ass and requires no
proof, I mention these isolated criticisms to show that the
Elements, although they superseded all other Elements and
never in ancient times had any rival, were not even at the
first accepted without question.
The first Latin author to mention Euclid is Cicero; but
it is not likely that the Elements had then been translated
into Latin. Theoretical geometry did not appeal to the
Romans, who only cared for so much of it as was useful for
measurements and calculations. Philosophers studied Euclid,
but probably in the original Greek ; Martianus Capella speaks
of the effect of the mention of the proposition ‘ how to con
struct an equilateral triangle on a given straight line ’ among
a company of philosophers, who, recognizing the first pro
position of the Elements, straightway break out into encomiums
on Euclid. 2 Beyond a fragment in a Verona palimpsest of
a free rendering or rearrangement of some propositions from
Books XII and XIII dating apparently from the fourth century,
we have no trace of any Latin version before Boëtius (born
about A. d. 480), to whom Magnus Aurelius Cassiodorus and
Theodoric attribute a translation of Euclid. The so-called
geometry of Boëtius which has come down to us is by no
means a translation of Euclid ; but even the redaction of this
in two Books which was edited by Friedlein is not genuine,
having apparently been put together in the eleventh century
from various sources ; it contains the definitions of Book I,
the Postulates (five in number), the Axioms (three only), then
some definitions from Eucl. II, III, TV, followed by the
enunciations only (without proofs) of Eucl. I, ten propositions
Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 200. 2.
2 Mart. Capella, vi. 724,