378
EUCLID
proves that the sum ot‘ the three angles of a triangle is equal
to two right angles by means of a parallel to one side drawn
from the opposite vertex (cf. the slightly different Pytha
gorean proof, p. 143).
The third group of propositions (33-48) deals generally
with parallelograms, triangles and squares with reference to
their areas. 33, 34 amount to the proof of the existence and
the property of a parallelogram, and then we are introduced
to a new conception, that of equivalent figures, or figures
equal in area though not equal in the sense of congruent :
parallelograms on the same base or on equal bases and between
the same parallels are equal in area (35, 36) ; the same is true
of triangles (37, 38), and a parallelogram on the same (or an
equal) base with a triangle and between the same parallels is
double of the triangle (41). 39 and the interpolated 40 are
partial converses of 37 and 38. The theorem 41 enables us
‘ to construct in a given rectilineal angle a parallelogram
equal to a given triangle’ (42). Propositions 44, 45 are of
the greatest importance, being the first cases of the Pytha
gorean method of ‘ application of areas ’, £ to apply to a given
straight line, in a given rectilineal angle, a parallelogram
equal to a given triangle (or rectilineal figure) The con
struction in 44 is remarkably ingenious, being based'on that
of 42 combined with the proposition (43) proving that the
‘ complements of the parallelograms about the diameter ’ in any
parallelogram are equal. We are thus enabled to transform
a parallelogram of any shape into another with the same
angle and of equal area but with one side of any given length,
say a unit length ; this is the geometrical equivalent of the
algebraic operation of dividing the product of two quantities
by a third. Proposition 46 constructs a square on any given
straight line as side, and is followed by the great Pythagorean
theorem of the square on the hypotenuse of a right-angled
triangle (47) and its converse (48). The remarkably clever
proof of 47 by means of the well-known ‘windmill’ figure
and the application to it of I. 41 combined with I. 4 seems to
be due to Euclid himself ; it is really equivalent to a proof by
the methods of Book VI (Propositions 8, 17), and Euclid’s
achievement was that of avoiding the use of proportions and
making the proof dependent upon Book I only.