Full text: From Thales to Euclid (Volume 1)

THE ELEMENTS. BOOK V 
389 
_ 
we have ma : mb — no ; nd, (H) 
whence (14), according as ma > = < no, mb > = < nd ; 
therefore (Def. 5) a : c = h : d. 
17. If a:b = c:d, 
then, separando, {a — b) : b = (c — d) : d. 
Take met, mb, me, md equimultiples of all four magnitudes, 
and nb, nd other equimultiples of b, d. It follows (2) that 
(m + n) b, (m + n)d are also equimultiples of b, d. 
Therefore, since a:h = c :d, 
ma > = <{m + n)b according as me > = <(m + n) d. (Def. 5) 
Subtracting mb from both sides of the former relation and 
md from both sides of the latter, we have (5) 
m (a — b) > = < nb according as m (c — d) > = < nd. 
Therefore (Def. 5) a — b:b = c — d:d. 
(I have here abbreviated Euclid a little, without altering the 
substance.) 
18. If a : b = c : d, 
then, componendo, {a + b):b = (c + d):d. 
Proved by reductio ad absurdum. Euclid assumes that 
a + h:b = (c + d): (d±x), if that is possible. (This implies 
that to any three given magnitudes, two of which at least 
are of the same kind, there exists a fourth proportional, an 
assumption which is not strictly legitimate until the fact has 
been proved by construction.) 
Therefore, separando (17), a\b — (c + x) : (d±x), 
whence (11), (c + x) : {d ± x) = c : d, which relations are im 
possible, by 14. 
19. If a:b = c:d, 
then (a — c) : (b — d) = a:b. 
Alternately (16), 
a:c = b:d, whence (a — c):c = (b—d):d (17). 
Alternately again, (a — c):{b — d) = c:d (16) ; 
whence (11) (a — c):{b — d) = a:b.
	        
Waiting...

Note to user

Dear user,

In response to current developments in the web technology used by the Goobi viewer, the software no longer supports your browser.

Please use one of the following browsers to display this page correctly.

Thank you.