588
A SIXTH MEMOIR UPON QUANTICS.
[158
218. And we may from the first formula of either set, deduce for the distance
of the point (x, y, z) and the line (£', y, £"), the expression
sin“ 1 V K (£x + yy + %'z)
V(a, y, zf V(&, 77', O 2 ’
as may be easily seen by writing + Ji%y' + for x', y\ z, or ax + hy + gz,... for
77, £, and putting sin -1 for cos -1 .
219. It may be noticed that there are certain lines, viz. the tangents of the
Absolute, in regard to which, considered as a space of one dimension, the Absolute is
a pair of coincident points; and in like manner certain points, viz. the ineunts of
the Absolute, in regard to which, considered as a space of one dimension, the Absolute
is a pair of coincident lines.
220. We may, in particular, suppose that the Absolute, instead of being a proper
conic, is a pair of points. The line through the two points may be called the Absolute
line; such line is to be considered as a pair of coincident lines. Any point what
ever determines with the Absolute, two lines, viz. the lines joining the point with
the two points of the Absolute; this line-pair is the Absolute for the point con
sidered as a space of one dimension or locus in quo of a pencil of lines, and the
theory of the distances of lines through a point is therefore precisely the same as in
the general case. But any line whatever determines with the Absolute (meets the
Absolute line in) a pair of coincident points, which pair of coincident points is the
Absolute in regard to such line considered as a space of one dimension or locus in
quo of a range of points, and the theory of the distance of points on a line is
therefore the theory before explained for this special case. But we cannot, in the
same way as before, compare the distances of points upon different lines, since we have
not in the present case the quadrant as a unit of distance. The comparison must
be made by means of the circle, viz. in the present case any conic passing through
the two points of the Absolute is termed a circle, and the point of intersection of
the tangents to the circle at the two points of the Absolute (or what is the same
thing, the pole of the Absolute line in respect to the circle) is the centre of the
circle. The Absolute line itself may, if it is necessary to do so, be considered as the
axis of the circle. It is assumed that the points of the circle are all of them
equidistant from the centre, and by this assumption we are enabled to compare
distances upon different lines. In fact we may, by a construction precisely similar to
that of Euclid, Book I. Prop. II., from a given point A draw a finite line equal to
a given finite line BC, and thence also upon a given line through A, determine the
finite line AD equal to the given finite line BG. Since the unit of distance for
points on a line is arbitrary, we cannot of course compare the distances of points
with the distances of lines. The distance of a point from a line does, however, admit
of comparison with the distance of two points; we have only to assume as a definition
that the distance of a point from a line is the distance of the point from the point
of intersection of the line with the quadrantal line through the point.