Full text: The collected mathematical papers of Arthur Cayley, Sc.D., F.R.S., late sadlerian professor of pure mathematics in the University of Cambridge (Vol. 11)

436 
PRESIDENTIAL ADDRESS TO THE 
[784 
acceptation of the term, but in quite a different acceptation. Or in a somewhat different 
way: if the rate of progress from a given point in a given direction be conceived as 
depending only on the configuration of the ground, and the distance along a given path 
between any two points thereof be measured by the time required for traversing it, then 
in this way also the distance would have a perfectly determinate value; but it would be 
a distance, not in the ordinary acceptation of the term, but in quite a different 
acceptation. And corresponding to the new notion of distance we should have a new 
non-Euclidian system of plane geometry; all theorems involving the notion of distance 
would be altered. 
We may proceed further. Suppose that as the rule moves away from a fixed 
central point of the plane it becomes shorter and shorter; if this shortening takes 
place with sufficient rapidity, it may very well be that a distance which in the ordinary 
sense of the word is finite will in the new sense be infinite ; no number of repetitions 
of the length of the ever-shortening rule will be sufficient to cover it. There will be 
surrounding the central point a certain finite area such that (in the new acceptation 
of the term distance) each point of the boundary thereof will be at an infinite distance 
from the central point; the points outside this area you cannot by any means arrive at 
with your rule; they will form a terra incognita, or rather an unknowable land: in 
mathematical language, an imaginary or impossible space: and the plane space of the 
theory will be that within the finite area—that is, it will be finite instead of 
infinite. 
We thus with a proper law of shortening arrive at a system of non-Euclidian 
geometry which is essentially that of Lobatschewsky. But in so obtaining it we put 
out of sight its relation to spherical geometry: the three geometries (spherical, Euclidian, 
and Lobatschewsky’s) should be regarded as members of a system: viz. they are the 
geometries of a plane (two-dimensional) space of constant positive curvature, zero 
curvature, and constant negative curvature respectively; or again, they are the plane 
geometries corresponding to three different notions of distance; in this point of view 
they are Klein’s elliptic, parabolic, and hyperbolic geometries respectively. 
Next as regards solid geometry: we can by a modification of the notion of distance 
(such as has just been explained in regard to Lobatschewsky’s system) pass from our 
present system to a non-Euclidian system; for the other mode of passing to a non- 
Euclidian system, it would be necessary to regard our space as a flat three-dimensional 
space existing in a space of four dimensions (i.e., as the analogue of a plane existing in 
ordinary space); and to substitute for such flat three-dimensional space a curved three- 
dimensional space, say of constant positive or negative curvature. In regarding the 
physical space of our experience as possibly non-Euclidian, Biemann’s idea seems to be 
that of modifying the notion of distance, not that of treating it as a locus in four 
dimensional space. 
I have just come to speak of four-dimensional space. What meaning do we attach 
to it ? Or can we attach to it any meaning ? It may be at once admitted that we 
cannot conceive of a fourth dimension of space; that space as we conceive of it, and 
the physical space of our experience, are alike three-dimensional; but we can, I think, 
conceive of space as being two- or even one-dimensional; we can imagine rational
	        
Waiting...

Note to user

Dear user,

In response to current developments in the web technology used by the Goobi viewer, the software no longer supports your browser.

Please use one of the following browsers to display this page correctly.

Thank you.