438
PRESIDENTIAL ADDRESS TO THE
[784
other root is = — i) and it is easily seen that every quadric equation (with real
coefficients as before) has two roots, a + bi, where a and 6 are real magnitudes. We
are thus led to the conception of an imaginary magnitude, a + hi, where a and b are
real magnitudes, each susceptible of any positive or negative value, zero included. The
general theorem is that, taking the coefficients of the equation to be imaginary magni
tudes, then an equation of the order n has always n roots, each of them an imaginary
magnitude, and it thus appears that the foregoing form a + hi of imaginary magnitude
is the only one that presents itself. Such imaginary magnitudes may be added or
multiplied together or dealt with in any manner; the result is always a like imaginary
magnitude. They are thus the magnitudes which are considered in analysis, and
analysis is the science of such magnitudes. Observe the leading character that the
imaginary magnitude a + bi is a magnitude composed of the two real magnitudes a and
b (in the case 6 = 0 it is the real magnitude a, and in the case a = 0 it is the pure
imaginary magnitude bi). The idea is that of considering, in place of real magnitudes,
these imaginary or complex magnitudes a + bi.
In the Cartesian geometry a curve is determined by means of the equation
existing between the coordinates {x, y) of any point thereof. In the case of a right
line, this equation is linear; in the case of a circle, or more generally of a conic, the
equation is of the second order; and generally, when the equation is of the order n,
the curve which it represents is said to be a curve of the order n. In the case of
two given curves, there are thus two equations satisfied by the coordinates (x, y) of the
several points of intersection, and these give rise to an equation of a certain order for
the coordinate x or y of a point of intersection. In the case of a straight line and a
circle, this is a quadric equation; it has two roots, real or imaginary. There are thus
two values, say of x, and to each of these corresponds a single value of y. There are
therefore two points of intersection—viz. a straight line and a circle intersect always
in two points, real or imaginary. It is in this way that we are led analytically to the
notion of imaginary points in geometry. The conclusion as to the two points of
intersection cannot be contradicted by experience: take a sheet of paper and draw
on it the straight line and circle, and try. But you might say, or at least be strongly
tempted to say, that it is meaningless. The question of course arises, What is the
meaning of an imaginary point ? and further, In what manner can the notion be
arrived at geometrically ?
There is a well-known construction in perspective for drawing lines through the
intersection of two lines, which are so nearly parallel as not to meet within the limits
of the sheet of paper. You have two given lines which do not meet, and you draw
a third line, which, when the lines are all of them produced, is found to pass through
the intersection of the given lines. If instead of lines we have two circular arcs not
meeting each other, then we can, by means of these arcs, construct a line; and if
on completing the circles it is found that the circles intersect each other in two real
points, then it will be found that the line passes through these two points: if the
circles appear not to intersect, then the line will appear not to intersect either of the
circles. But the geometrical construction being in each case the same, we say that
in the second case also the line passes through the two intersections of the circles.